Loading AI tools
Hierarchy of complexity classes for formulas defining sets From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In mathematical logic, the arithmetical hierarchy, arithmetic hierarchy or Kleene–Mostowski hierarchy (after mathematicians Stephen Cole Kleene and Andrzej Mostowski) classifies certain sets based on the complexity of formulas that define them. Any set that receives a classification is called arithmetical. The arithmetical hierarchy was invented independently by Kleene (1943) and Mostowski (1946).[1]
This article includes a list of references, related reading, or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations. (June 2021) |
The arithmetical hierarchy is important in computability theory, effective descriptive set theory, and the study of formal theories such as Peano arithmetic.
The Tarski–Kuratowski algorithm provides an easy way to get an upper bound on the classifications assigned to a formula and the set it defines.
The hyperarithmetical hierarchy and the analytical hierarchy extend the arithmetical hierarchy to classify additional formulas and sets.
The arithmetical hierarchy assigns classifications to the formulas in the language of first-order arithmetic. The classifications are denoted and for natural numbers n (including 0). The Greek letters here are lightface symbols, which indicates that the formulas do not contain set parameters.[clarification needed]
If a formula is logically equivalent to a formula having no unbounded quantifiers, i.e. in which all quantifiers are bounded quantifiers then is assigned the classifications and .
The classifications and are defined inductively for every natural number n using the following rules:
A formula is equivalent to a formula that begins with some existential quantifiers and alternates times between series of existential and universal quantifiers; while a formula is equivalent to a formula that begins with some universal quantifiers and alternates analogously.
Because every first-order formula has a prenex normal form, every formula is assigned at least one classification. Because redundant quantifiers can be added to any formula, once a formula is assigned the classification or it will be assigned the classifications and for every m > n. The only relevant classification assigned to a formula is thus the one with the least n; all the other classifications can be determined from it.
A set X of natural numbers is defined by a formula φ in the language of Peano arithmetic (the first-order language with symbols "0" for zero, "S" for the successor function, "+" for addition, "×" for multiplication, and "=" for equality), if the elements of X are exactly the numbers that satisfy φ. That is, for all natural numbers n,
where is the numeral in the language of arithmetic corresponding to . A set is definable in first-order arithmetic if it is defined by some formula in the language of Peano arithmetic.
Each set X of natural numbers that is definable in first-order arithmetic is assigned classifications of the form , , and , where is a natural number, as follows. If X is definable by a formula then X is assigned the classification . If X is definable by a formula then X is assigned the classification . If X is both and then is assigned the additional classification .
Note that it rarely makes sense to speak of formulas; the first quantifier of a formula is either existential or universal. So a set is not necessarily defined by a formula in the sense of a formula that is both and ; rather, there are both and formulas that define the set. For example, the set of odd natural numbers is definable by either or .
A parallel definition is used to define the arithmetical hierarchy on finite Cartesian powers of the set of natural numbers. Instead of formulas with one free variable, formulas with k free first-order variables are used to define the arithmetical hierarchy on sets of k-tuples of natural numbers. These are in fact related by the use of a pairing function.
The following meanings can be attached to the notation for the arithmetical hierarchy on formulas.
The subscript in the symbols and indicates the number of alternations of blocks of universal and existential first-order quantifiers that are used in a formula. Moreover, the outermost block is existential in formulas and universal in formulas.
The superscript in the symbols , , and indicates the type of the objects being quantified over. Type 0 objects are natural numbers, and objects of type are functions that map the set of objects of type to the natural numbers. Quantification over higher type objects, such as functions from natural numbers to natural numbers, is described by a superscript greater than 0, as in the analytical hierarchy. The superscript 0 indicates quantifiers over numbers, the superscript 1 would indicate quantification over functions from numbers to numbers (type 1 objects), the superscript 2 would correspond to quantification over functions that take a type 1 object and return a number, and so on.
Just as we can define what it means for a set X to be recursive relative to another set Y by allowing the computation defining X to consult Y as an oracle we can extend this notion to the whole arithmetic hierarchy and define what it means for X to be , or in Y, denoted respectively , and . To do so, fix a set of natural numbers Y and add a predicate for membership of Y to the language of Peano arithmetic. We then say that X is in if it is defined by a formula in this expanded language. In other words, X is if it is defined by a formula allowed to ask questions about membership of Y. Alternatively one can view the sets as those sets that can be built starting with sets recursive in Y and alternately taking unions and intersections of these sets up to n times.
For example, let Y be a set of natural numbers. Let X be the set of numbers divisible by an element of Y. Then X is defined by the formula so X is in (actually it is in as well, since we could bound both quantifiers by n).
Arithmetical reducibility is an intermediate notion between Turing reducibility and hyperarithmetic reducibility.
A set is arithmetical (also arithmetic and arithmetically definable) if it is defined by some formula in the language of Peano arithmetic. Equivalently X is arithmetical if X is or for some natural number n. A set X is arithmetical in a set Y, denoted , if X is definable as some formula in the language of Peano arithmetic extended by a predicate for membership of Y. Equivalently, X is arithmetical in Y if X is in or for some natural number n. A synonym for is: X is arithmetically reducible to Y.
The relation is reflexive and transitive, and thus the relation defined by the rule
is an equivalence relation. The equivalence classes of this relation are called the arithmetic degrees; they are partially ordered under .
The Cantor space, denoted , is the set of all infinite sequences of 0s and 1s; the Baire space, denoted or , is the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers. Note that elements of the Cantor space can be identified with sets of natural numbers and elements of the Baire space with functions from natural numbers to natural numbers.
The ordinary axiomatization of second-order arithmetic uses a set-based language in which the set quantifiers can naturally be viewed as quantifying over Cantor space. A subset of Cantor space is assigned the classification if it is definable by a formula. The set is assigned the classification if it is definable by a formula. If the set is both and then it is given the additional classification . For example, let be the set of all infinite binary strings that aren't all 0 (or equivalently the set of all non-empty sets of natural numbers). As we see that is defined by a formula and hence is a set.
Note that while both the elements of the Cantor space (regarded as sets of natural numbers) and subsets of the Cantor space are classified in arithmetic hierarchies, these are not the same hierarchy. In fact the relationship between the two hierarchies is interesting and non-trivial. For instance the elements of the Cantor space are not (in general) the same as the elements of the Cantor space so that is a subset of the Cantor space. However, many interesting results relate the two hierarchies.
There are two ways that a subset of Baire space can be classified in the arithmetical hierarchy.
A parallel definition is used to define the arithmetical hierarchy on finite Cartesian powers of Baire space or Cantor space, using formulas with several free variables. The arithmetical hierarchy can be defined on any effective Polish space; the definition is particularly simple for Cantor space and Baire space because they fit with the language of ordinary second-order arithmetic.
Note that we can also define the arithmetic hierarchy of subsets of the Cantor and Baire spaces relative to some set of natural numbers. In fact boldface is just the union of for all sets of natural numbers Y. Note that the boldface hierarchy is just the standard hierarchy of Borel sets.
It is possible to define the arithmetical hierarchy of formulas using a language extended with a function symbol for each primitive recursive function. This variation slightly changes the classification of , since using primitive recursive functions in first-order Peano arithmetic requires, in general, an unbounded existential quantifier, and thus some sets that are in by this definition are strictly in by the definition given in the beginning of this article. The class and thus all higher classes in the hierarchy remain unaffected.
A more semantic variation of the hierarchy can be defined on all finitary relations on the natural numbers; the following definition is used. Every computable relation is defined to be . The classifications and are defined inductively with the following rules.
This variation slightly changes the classification of some sets. In particular, , as a class of sets (definable by the relations in the class), is identical to as the latter was formerly defined. It can be extended to cover finitary relations on the natural numbers, Baire space, and Cantor space.
The following properties hold for the arithmetical hierarchy of sets of natural numbers and the arithmetical hierarchy of subsets of Cantor or Baire space.
If S is a Turing computable set, then both S and its complement are recursively enumerable (if T is a Turing machine giving 1 for inputs in S and 0 otherwise, we may build a Turing machine halting only on the former, and another halting only on the latter).
By Post's theorem, both S and its complement are in . This means that S is both in and in , and hence it is in .
Similarly, for every set S in , both S and its complement are in and are therefore (by Post's theorem) recursively enumerable by some Turing machines T1 and T2, respectively. For every number n, exactly one of these halts. We may therefore construct a Turing machine T that alternates between T1 and T2, halting and returning 1 when the former halts or halting and returning 0 when the latter halts. Thus T halts on every n and returns whether it is in S; so S is computable.
The Turing computable sets of natural numbers are exactly the sets at level of the arithmetical hierarchy. The recursively enumerable sets are exactly the sets at level .
No oracle machine is capable of solving its own halting problem (a variation of Turing's proof applies). The halting problem for a oracle in fact sits in .
Post's theorem establishes a close connection between the arithmetical hierarchy of sets of natural numbers and the Turing degrees. In particular, it establishes the following facts for all n ≥ 1:
The polynomial hierarchy is a "feasible resource-bounded" version of the arithmetical hierarchy in which polynomial length bounds are placed on the numbers involved (or, equivalently, polynomial time bounds are placed on the Turing machines involved). It gives a finer classification of some sets of natural numbers that are at level of the arithmetical hierarchy.
Lightface | Boldface | ||
---|---|---|---|
Σ0 0 = Π0 0 = Δ0 0 (sometimes the same as Δ0 1) |
Σ0 0 = Π0 0 = Δ0 0 (if defined) | ||
Δ0 1 = recursive |
Δ0 1 = clopen | ||
Σ0 1 = recursively enumerable |
Π0 1 = co-recursively enumerable |
Σ0 1 = G = open |
Π0 1 = F = closed |
Δ0 2 |
Δ0 2 | ||
Σ0 2 |
Π0 2 |
Σ0 2 = Fσ |
Π0 2 = Gδ |
Δ0 3 |
Δ0 3 | ||
Σ0 3 |
Π0 3 |
Σ0 3 = Gδσ |
Π0 3 = Fσδ |
⋮ | ⋮ | ||
Σ0 <ω = Π0 <ω = Δ0 <ω = Σ1 0 = Π1 0 = Δ1 0 = arithmetical |
Σ0 <ω = Π0 <ω = Δ0 <ω = Σ1 0 = Π1 0 = Δ1 0 = boldface arithmetical | ||
⋮ | ⋮ | ||
Δ0 α (α recursive) |
Δ0 α (α countable) | ||
Σ0 α |
Π0 α |
Σ0 α |
Π0 α |
⋮ | ⋮ | ||
Σ0 ωCK 1 = Π0 ωCK 1 = Δ0 ωCK 1 = Δ1 1 = hyperarithmetical |
Σ0 ω1 = Π0 ω1 = Δ0 ω1 = Δ1 1 = B = Borel | ||
Σ1 1 = lightface analytic |
Π1 1 = lightface coanalytic |
Σ1 1 = A = analytic |
Π1 1 = CA = coanalytic |
Δ1 2 |
Δ1 2 | ||
Σ1 2 |
Π1 2 |
Σ1 2 = PCA |
Π1 2 = CPCA |
Δ1 3 |
Δ1 3 | ||
Σ1 3 |
Π1 3 |
Σ1 3 = PCPCA |
Π1 3 = CPCPCA |
⋮ | ⋮ | ||
Σ1 <ω = Π1 <ω = Δ1 <ω = Σ2 0 = Π2 0 = Δ2 0 = analytical |
Σ1 <ω = Π1 <ω = Δ1 <ω = Σ2 0 = Π2 0 = Δ2 0 = P = projective | ||
⋮ | ⋮ |
Seamless Wikipedia browsing. On steroids.
Every time you click a link to Wikipedia, Wiktionary or Wikiquote in your browser's search results, it will show the modern Wikiwand interface.
Wikiwand extension is a five stars, simple, with minimum permission required to keep your browsing private, safe and transparent.